V.C. Müller
Publications
Home
Research
Publications
Teaching
Activities

 

Books
Papers
Theses
Miscellanea
Journalism & Interviews

 

My publications are listed below, with a link to the publisher, a link to a pdf for dowload, and an abstract <onmouseover>.

See also:
Google Scholar ... ca. 1 citation per day1
PhilPapers
ResearchGate
ORCID
'Terse CV' on this site


[word cloud of the abstracts in my publications below]

Books

Authored

  1. Müller, Vincent C. (forthcoming), Can machines think? Fundamental problems of artificial intelligence (New York: Oxford University Press). 250pp.
    [Publisher] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Artificial Intelligence (AI) has taken central stage in our imagination of the future. It raises fundamental questions about what it is to be human, what machines can do, and what the chances and risks of this technological development are. This book addresses these fundamental questions directly and seriously; both those that the general public is concerned about, and the ones people who develop AI are facing.

  2. Müller, Vincent C. and Löhr, Guido (forthcoming), Artificial minds, ed. Keith Frankish (Cambridge Elements - Philosophy of Mind; Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
    [Publisher] [Abstract]

Edited

  1. Müller, Vincent C. (ed.), (forthcoming), Oxford handbook of the philosophy of artificial intelligence (New York: Oxford University Press). 400pp.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]

  2. Müller, Vincent C. (ed.), (forthcoming), Philosophy and theory of artificial intelligence 2021 (SAPERE; Berlin: Springer).
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: "0"

  3. Vallverdú, Jordi and Müller, Vincent C. (eds.) (2019), Blended cognition: The robotic challenge (Springer Series in Cognitive and Neural Systems; Cham: Springer). 314
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: The central concept of this edited volume is "blended cognition", the natural skill of human beings for combining constantly different heuristics during their several task-solving activities. Something that was sometimes observed like a problem as “bad reasoning”, is now the central key for the understanding of the richness, adaptability and creativity of human cognition. The topic of this book connects in a significant way with the disciplines of psychology, neurology, anthropology, philosophy, logics, engineering, logics, and AI. In a nutshell: understanding better humans for designing better machines. It contains a Preface by the editors and 12 chapters.'"

  4. Chrisley, Ron; Müller, Vincent C.; Sandamirskaya, Yulia and Vincze, Markus (eds.) (2019), Cognitive robot architectures (Cognitive Systems Research: Special Issue, 55; Amsterdam: Elsevier), 107-45.
    [Publisher] [Abstract]

  5. Müller, Vincent C. (ed.), (2018), Philosophy and theory of artificial intelligence 2017 (SAPERE, 44; Berlin: Springer). 325 pp.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: This book reports on the results of the third edition of the premier conference in the field of philosophy of artificial intelligence, PT-AI 2017, held on November 4 - 5, 2017 at the University of Leeds, UK. It covers: advanced knowledge on key AI concepts, including complexity, computation, creativity, embodiment, representation and superintelligence; cutting-edge ethical issues, such as the AI impact on human dignity and society, responsibilities and rights of machines, as well as AI threats to humanity and AI safety; and cutting-edge developments in techniques to achieve AI, including machine learning, neural networks, dynamical systems. The book also discusses important applications of AI, including big data analytics, expert systems, cognitive architectures, and robotics. It offers a timely, yet very comprehensive snapshot of what is going on in the field of AI, especially at the interfaces between philosophy, cognitive science, ethics and computing.'"

  6. Chrisley, Ron; Müller, Vincent C.; Sandamirskaya, Yulia and Vincze, Markus (eds.) (2017), Cognitive robot architectures: Proceedings of EUCognition 2016 (CEUR-WS, 1855; Hamburg: CEUR). 70pp
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: The European Association for Cognitive Systems is the association resulting from the EUCog network, which has been active since 2006. It has ca. 1000 members and is currently chaired by Vincent C. Müller. We ran our annual conference on December 08-09 2016, kindly hosted by the Technical University of Vienna with Markus Vincze as local chair. The invited speakers were David Vernon and Paul F.M.J. Verschure. Out of the 49 submissions for the meeting, we accepted 18 a papers and 25 as posters (after double-blind reviewing). Papers are published here as “full papers” or “short papers” while posters are published here as “short papers” or “abstracts”. Some of the papers presented at the conference will be published in a separate special volume on ‘Cognitive Robot Architectures’ with the journal Cognitive Systems Research. - RC, VCM, YS, MV'"

  7. Müller, Vincent C. (ed.), (2016), Computing and philosophy: Selected papers from IACAP 2014 (Synthese Library, 375; Berlin: Springer). 282 pp.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: This volume offers very selected papers from the 2014 conference of the “International Association for Computing and Philosophy” (IACAP) - a conference tradition of 28 years. - - - Table of Contents - 0 Vincent C. Müller: - Editorial - 1) Philosophy of computing - 1 Çem Bozsahin: - What is a computational constraint? - 2 Joe Dewhurst: - Computing Mechanisms and Autopoietic Systems - 3 Vincenzo Fano, Pierluigi Graziani, Roberto Macrelli and Gino Tarozzi: - Are Gandy Machines really local? - 4 Doukas Kapantais: - A refutation of the Church-Turing thesis according to some interpretation of what the thesis says - 5 Paul Schweizer: - In What Sense Does the Brain Compute? - 2) Philosophy of computer science & discovery - 6 Mark Addis, Peter Sozou, Peter C R Lane and Fernand Gobet: - Computational Scientific Discovery and Cognitive Science Theories - 7 Nicola Angius and Petros Stefaneas: - Discovering Empirical Theories of Modular Software Systems. An Algebraic Approach. - 8 Selmer Bringsjord, John Licato, Daniel Arista, Naveen Sundar Govindarajulu and Paul Bello: - Introducing the Doxastically Centered Approach to Formalizing Relevance Bonds in Conditionals - 9 Orly Stettiner: - From Silico to Vitro: - Computational Models of Complex Biological Systems Reveal Real-world Emergent Phenomena - 3) Philosophy of cognition & intelligence - 10 Douglas Campbell: - Why We Shouldn’t Reason Classically, and the Implications for Artificial Intelligence - 11 Stefano Franchi: - Cognition as Higher Order Regulation - 12 Marcello Guarini: - Eliminativisms, Languages of Thought, & the Philosophy of Computational Cognitive Modeling - 13 Marcin Miłkowski: - A Mechanistic Account of Computational Explanation in Cognitive Science and Computational Neuroscience - 14 Alex Tillas: - Internal supervision & clustering: - A new lesson from ‘old’ findings? - 4) Computing & society - 15 Vasileios Galanos: - Floridi/Flusser: - Parallel Lives in Hyper/Posthistory - 16 Paul Bello: - Machine Ethics and Modal Psychology - 17 Marty J. Wolf and Nir Fresco: - My Liver Is Broken, Can You Print Me a New One? - 18 Marty J. Wolf, Frances Grodzinsky and Keith W. Miller: - Robots, Ethics and Software – FOSS vs. Proprietary Licenses'"

  8. Müller, Vincent C. (ed.), (2016), Fundamental issues of artificial intelligence (Synthese Library, 377; Berlin: Springer). 570 pp.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: PT-AI 2013: This volume offers a look at the fundamental issues of present and future AI, especially from cognitive science, computer science, neuroscience and philosophy. This work examines the conditions for artificial intelligence, how these relate to the conditions for intelligence in humans and other natural agents, as well as ethical and societal problems that artificial intelligence raises or will raise. The key issues this volume investigates include the relation of AI and cognitive science, ethics of AI and robotics, brain emulation and simulation, hybrid systems and cyborgs, intelligence and intelligence testing, interactive systems, multi-agent systems, and superintelligence. Based on the 2nd conference on “Theory and Philosophy of Artificial Intelligence” held in Oxford, the volume includes prominent researchers within the field from around the world.'"

  9. Müller, Vincent C. (ed.), (2016), Risks of artificial intelligence (London: Chapman & Hall - CRC Press). 292 pp.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Papers from the conference on AI Impacts (published in JETAI), supplemented by additional work. Müller, Vincent C. If the intelligence of artificial systems were to surpass that of humans, humanity would face significant risks. The time has come to consider these issues, and this consideration must include progress in artificial intelligence (AI) as much as insights from AI theory. -- Featuring contributions from leading experts and thinkers in artificial intelligence, Risks of Artificial Intelligence is the first volume of collected chapters dedicated to examining the risks of AI. The book evaluates predictions of the future of AI, proposes ways to ensure that AI systems will be beneficial to humans, and then critically evaluates such proposals. 1 Vincent C. Müller, Editorial: Risks of Artificial Intelligence - 2 Steve Omohundro, Autonomous Technology and the Greater Human Good - 3 Stuart Armstrong, Kaj Sotala and Sean O’Heigeartaigh, The Errors, Insights and Lessons of Famous AI Predictions - and What they Mean for the Future - 4 Ted Goertzel, The Path to More General Artificial Intelligence - 5 Miles Brundage, Limitations and Risks of Machine Ethics - 6 Roman Yampolskiy, Utility Function Security in Artificially Intelligent Agents - 7 Ben Goertzel, GOLEM: Toward an AGI Meta-Architecture Enabling Both Goal Preservation and Radical Self-Improvement - 8 Alexey Potapov and Sergey Rodionov, Universal Empathy and Ethical Bias for Artificial General Intelligence - 9 András Kornai, Bounding the Impact of AGI - 10 Anders Sandberg, Ethics and Impact of Brain Emulations 11 Daniel Dewey, Long-Term Strategies for Ending Existential Risk from Fast Takeoff - 12 Mark Bishop, The Singularity, or How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Love AI -'"

  10. Müller, Vincent C. (ed.), (2014), Risks of artificial general intelligence (Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence, (26/3) Special Issue: Taylor & Francis). 160 pp.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Special Issue “Risks of artificial general intelligence”, Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence, 26/3 (2014), ed. Vincent C. Müller. http://www.tandfonline.com/toc/teta20/26/3# - Risks of general artificial intelligence, Vincent C. Müller, pages 297-301 - Autonomous technology and the greater human good - Steve Omohundro - pages 303-315 - - - The errors, insights and lessons of famous AI predictions – and what they mean for the future - Stuart Armstrong, Kaj Sotala & Seán S. Ó hÉigeartaigh - pages 317-342 - - - The path to more general artificial intelligence - Ted Goertzel - pages 343-354 - - - Limitations and risks of machine ethics - Miles Brundage - pages 355-372 - - - Utility function security in artificially intelligent agents - Roman V. Yampolskiy - pages 373-389 - - - GOLEM: towards an AGI meta-architecture enabling both goal preservation and radical self-improvement - Ben Goertzel - pages 391-403 - - - Universal empathy and ethical bias for artificial general intelligence - Alexey Potapov & Sergey Rodionov - pages 405-416 - - - Bounding the impact of AGI - András Kornai - pages 417-438 - - - Ethics of brain emulations - Anders Sandberg - pages 439-457'"

  11. Müller, Vincent C. (ed.), (2013), Philosophy and theory of artificial intelligence (SAPERE, 5; Berlin: Springer). 429 pp.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Can we make machines that think and act like humans or other natural intelligent agents? The answer to this question depends on how we see ourselves and how we see the machines in question. Classical AI and cognitive science had claimed that cognition is computation, and can thus be reproduced on other computing machines, possibly surpassing the abilities of human intelligence. This consensus has now come under threat and the agenda for the philosophy and theory of AI must be set anew, re-defining the relation between AI and Cognitive Science. We can re-claim the original vision of general AI from the technical AI disciplines; we can reject classical cognitive science and replace it with a new theory (e.g. embodied); or we can try to find new ways to approach AI, for example from neuroscience or from systems theory. To do this, we must go back to the basic questions on computing, cognition and ethics for AI. The 30 papers in this volume provide cutting-edge work from leading researchers that define where we stand and where we should go from here. (Published 10/2012.)'"

  12. Müller, Vincent C. and Ayesh, Aladdin (eds.) (2012), Revisiting Turing and his test: Comprehensiveness, qualia, and the real world (AISB Proceedings, 7/2012; Hove: AISB). 64 pp.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Proceedings of the papers presented at the Symposium on "Revisiting Turing and his Test: Comprehensiveness, Qualia, and the Real World" at the 2012 AISB and IACAP Symposium that was held in the Turing year 2012, 2–6 July at the University of Birmingham, UK. Ten papers. - http://www.pt-ai.org/turing-test Müller, Vincent C. Daniel Devatman Hromada: From Taxonomy of Turing Test-Consistent Scenarios Towards Attribution of Legal Status to Meta-modular Artificial Autonomous Agents - Michael Zillich: My Robot is Smarter than Your Robot: On the Need for a Total Turing Test for Robots - Adam Linson, Chris Dobbyn and Robin Laney: Interactive Intelligence: Behaviour-based AI, Musical HCI and the Turing Test - Javier Insa, Jose Hernandez-Orallo, Sergio España - David Dowe and M.Victoria Hernandez-Lloreda: The anYnt Project Intelligence Test (Demo) - Jose Hernandez-Orallo, Javier Insa, David Dowe and Bill Hibbard: Turing Machines and Recursive Turing Tests — Francesco Bianchini and Domenica Bruni: What Language for Turing Test in the Age of Qualia? - Paul Schweizer: Could there be a Turing Test for Qualia? - Antonio Chella and Riccardo Manzotti: Jazz and Machine Consciousness: Towards a New Turing Test - William York and Jerry Swan: Taking Turing Seriously (But Not Literally) - Hajo Greif: Laws of Form and the Force of Function: Variations on the Turing Test.'"

  13. Müller, Vincent C. (ed.), (2012), Theory and philosophy of AI (Minds and Machines, 22/2 - Special volume: Springer). 67-148 pp.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Invited papers from PT-AI 2011. - Vincent C. Müller: Introduction: Theory and Philosophy of Artificial Intelligence - Nick Bostrom: The Superintelligent Will: Motivation and Instrumental Rationality in Advanced Artificial Agents - Hubert L. Dreyfus: A History of First Step Fallacies - Antoni Gomila, David Travieso and Lorena Lobo: Wherein is Human Cognition Systematic - J. Kevin O'Regan: How to Build a Robot that Is Conscious and Feels - Oron Shagrir: Computation, Implementation, Cognition'"

  14. Esposito, Anna; Esposito, Antonietta M; Hoffmann, Rüdiger; Müller, Vincent C. and Vinciarelli, Alessandro (eds.) (2012), Cognitive behavioural systems (LNCS, 7403; Berlin: Springer). 450 pp.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: This book constitutes refereed proceedings of the COST 2102 International Training School on Cognitive Behavioural Systems held in Dresden, Germany, in February 2011. The 39 revised full papers presented were carefully reviewed and selected from various submissions. The volume presents new and original research results in the field of human-machine interaction inspired by cognitive behavioural human-human interaction features. The themes covered are on cognitive and computational social information processing, emotional and social believable Human-Computer Interaction (HCI) systems, behavioural and contextual analysis of interaction, embodiment, perception, linguistics, semantics and sentiment analysis in dialogues and interactions, algorithmic and computational issues for the automatic recognition and synthesis of emotional states.'"

  15. Esposito, Anna; Esposito, Antonietta M; Martone, Raffaele; Müller, Vincent C. and Scarpetta, Gaetano (eds.) (2011), Towards autonomous, adaptive, and context-aware multimodal interfaces: Theoretical and practical issues (LNCS, 6456; Berlin: Springer). 474 pp.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: This volume brings together the advanced research results obtained by the European COST Action 2102: “Cross Modal Analysis of Verbal and Nonverbal Communication”. The research published in this book was discussed at the 3rd joint EUCOGII-COST 2102 International Training School entitled “Toward Autonomous, Adaptive, and Context-Aware Multimodal Interfaces: Theoretical and Practical Issues ” and held in Caserta, Italy, on March 15-19, 2010.'"

  16. Kazazis, Ioannis N; Müller, Vincent C. and Sistakou, Evina (eds.) (2003), Συμφραστικός πίνακας λέξεων στο ποιητικό έργο του Γιώργου Σεφέρη [Concordance to the poems of Georgios Seferis] (Thessaloniki: Centre for the Greek Language). 804 pp.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Concordance of the poetic works of Giorgos Seferis which presents all the principal “words” of the texts in an alphabetical list, stating how often each word occurs, giving a precise location and a relevant piece of text for each occurrence. We found ca. 9500 different Greek words in 39000 different occurrences, so our concordance has 50.000 lines of text. The technical procedure required four main steps: text entry and tagging, production of the concordance, correction of the contexts, formatting for print. '"

  17. Müller, Vincent C. (ed.), (1993), Hilary Putnam: Von einem realistischen Standpunkt, Schriften zu Sprache und Wirklichkeit [From a realist point of view: Writings on language and reality], trans. Vincent C. Müller (rowohlts enzyklopädie, 539; Reinbek: Rowohlt). 315 pp.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Einleitung 1 - Kritik des Positivismus: Realismus «Was kann ich wissen?» - 1 Erklärung und Referenz (1973) 1 - 2 Sprache und Wirklichkeit (1975) 38 - 3 Was ist ‹Realismus›? (1975) 77 - Der dritte Weg: Interer Realismus statt metaphysischem Realismus oder Positivismus - 4 Modelle und Wirklichkeit (1980) 112 - 5 Referenz und Wahrheit (1980) 159 - 6 Wie man zugleich interner Realist und transzendentaler Idealist sein kann (1980) 191 - 7 Warum es keine Fertigwelt gibt (1982) 218 - Auf des Messers Schneide: Interner Realismus und Relativismus - 8 Wozu die Philosophen? (1986) 259 - 9 Realismus mit menschlichem Antlitz (1988/90) 284 - 10 Irrealismus und Dekonstruktion (1992) 330 - Bibliographie der Schriften von Hilary Putnam 363 - I Bücher 363 - II Aufsätze, Vorträge und Vorlesungen 365 - III Übersetzungen ins Deutsche 385 - Literaturverzeichnis 387 - Register 413 - '"

  18. Krämer, Werner; Mathwig, Frank and Müller, Vincent C. (eds.) (1992-1998), Bücher zum Studium der evangelischen Theologie [Books for the study of protestant theology] (42, 43, 44, 45, 46, 47, 48 edn.; Marburg/Lahn: Timbuktu). 288 pp.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Vorbemerkung - Mit diesem kleinen roten Buch gibt Ihnen Ihre Buchhandlung eine Orientierung in der gegenwärtig lieferbaren theologischen Literatur an die Hand. In der vorliegenden Ausgabe im 47. Jahr 1997 ist die aktuelle Produktion von 158 Verlagen zur evangelischen Theologie sowie eine repräsentative Auswahl aus der katholischen Theologie, den Religionswissenschaften und der Philosophie verzeichnet, wobei der Schwerpunkt auf neuerer Literatur liegt. Die etwa 8000 Titel sind in thematische Kapitel eingeordnet und Neuerscheinungen mit einem *Sternchen gekennzeichnet. Das gut 4600 Namen umfassende Register erschließt Autoren, Herausgeber etc. ebenso wie das über eine Person vorhandene Schrifttum. Herausgegebene Werke finden sich unter ihrem Titel; Schriften, die als Teil einer Reihe erschienen sind, unter dem Titel der Reihe. - Wir danken den Buchhandlungen, die es erst ermöglichen, diese bibliographische Hilfe und Marktorientierung der interessierten Öffentlichkeit zur Verfügung zu stellen. Des weiteren danken wir den Verlagen für die Bereitstellung der Daten (oft aktueller als das VLB), insbesondere jenen Verlagen, die durch ihre Anzeigen zur Finanzierung dieses Projekts beitragen – siehe das Inserentenverzeichnis auf der letzten Seite. Trotz sorgfältiger Bearbeitung können wir für die Korrektheit der Angaben keine Garantie übernehmen. Wir hoffen, daß Ihnen unsere Arbeit nützlich ist und freuen uns über jede Art der Reaktion. Kontakt sowie Bestellung weiter Exemplare unter: - Timbuktu Verlag, Am Rain 20, 35039 Marburg, Telefon & Fax: 06421-62967, E-Mail: vcm@compuserve.com - Marburg, im März 1997 - Die Herausgeber - ISSN 0343-0251'"

Papers


  1. Müller, Vincent C. (forthcoming 2024), 'Philosophy of AI: A structured overview', in Nathalie A. Smuha (ed.), Cambridge handbook on the law, ethics and policy of Artificial Intelligence (Cambridge University Press), 1-25.
    [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: This paper presents the main topics, arguments, and positions in the philosophy of AI at present (excluding ethics). Apart from the basic concepts of intelligence and computation, the main topics of artificial cognition are perception, action, meaning, rational choice, free will, consciousness, and normativity. Through a better understanding of these topics, the philosophy of AI contributes to our understanding of the nature, prospects, and value of AI. Furthermore, these topics can be understood more deeply through the discussion of AI; so we suggest that “AI Philosophy” provides a new method for philosophy.'"

  2. Erler, Alexandre and Müller, Vincent C. (2024), 'AI as IA: The use and abuse of artificial intelligence (AI) for human enhancement through intellectual augmentation (IA)', in Marcello Ienca and Fabrice Jotterand (eds.), The Routledge handbook of the ethics of human enhancement' (London: Routledge), 187-99.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: This paper offers an overview of the prospects and ethics of using AI to achieve human enhancement, and more broadly what we call intellectual augmentation (IA). After explaining the central notions of human enhancement, IA, and AI, we discuss the state of the art in terms of the main technologies for IA, with or without brain-computer interfaces. Given this picture, we discuss potential ethical problems, namely inadequate performance, safety, coercion and manipulation, privacy, cognitive liberty, authenticity, and fairness in more detail. We conclude that while there are very significant technical hurdles to real human enhancement through AI, and significant ethical problems, there are also significant benefits that may realistically be achieved in ways that are consonant with a rights-based ethics as well. We also highlight the specific concerns that apply particularly to applications of AI for "sheer" IA (more realistic in the near term), and to enhancement applications, respectively.'"

  3. Müller, Vincent C. (2022), 'The history of digital ethics', in Carissa Véliz (ed.), Oxford handbook of digital ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Digital ethics, also known as computer ethics or information ethics, is now a lively field that draws a lot of attention, but how did it come about and what were the developments that lead to its existence? What are the traditions, the concerns, the technological and social developments that pushed digital ethics? How did ethical issues change with digitalisation of human life? How did the traditional discipline of philosophy respond? The article provides an overview, proposing historical epochs: ‘pre-modernity’ prior to digital computation over data, via the ‘modernity’ of digital data processing to our present ‘post-modernity’ when not only the data is digital, but our lives themselves are largely digital. In each section, the situation in technology and society is sketched, and then the developments in digital ethics are explained. Finally, a brief outlook is provided.'"

  4. Müller, Vincent C. (2022), 'Basic issues in AI policy', in Maria Amparo Grau-Ruiz (ed.), Interactive robotics: Legal, ethical, social and economic aspects (Biosystems & Biorobotics; Cham: Springer), 3-9.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]

  5. Müller, Vincent C. and Cannon, Michael (2022), 'Existential risk from AI and orthogonality: Can we have it both ways?', Ratio, 35 (1), 25-36.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: The standard argument to the conclusion that artificial intelligence (AI) constitutes an existential risk for the human species uses two premises: (1) AI may reach superintelligent levels, at which point we humans lose control (the ‘singularity claim’); (2) Any level of intelligence can go along with any goal (the ‘orthogonality thesis’). We find that the singularity claim requires a notion of ‘general intelligence’, while the orthogonality thesis requires a notion of ‘instrumental intelligence’. If this interpretation is correct, they cannot be joined as premises and the argument for the existential risk of AI turns out invalid. If the interpretation is incorrect and both premises use the same notion of intelligence, then at least one of the premises is false and the orthogonality thesis remains itself orthogonal to the argument to existential risk from AI. In either case, the standard argument for existential risk from AI is not sound.—Having said that, there remains a risk of instrumental AI to cause very significant damage if designed or used badly, though this is not due to superintelligence or a singularity.

  6. Müller, Vincent C. (2021), 'Ethics of artificial intelligence', in Anthony Elliott (ed.), The Routledge social science handbook of AI (London: Routledge), 122-37.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Artificial intelligence (AI) is a digital technology that will be of major importance for the development of humanity in the near future. AI has raised fundamental questions about what we should do with such systems, what the systems themselves should do, what risks they involve and how we can control these. - After the background to the field (1), this article introduces the main debates (2), first on ethical issues that arise with AI systems as objects, i.e. tools made and used by humans; here, the main sections are privacy (2.1), manipulation (2.2), opacity (2.3), bias (2.4), autonomy & responsibility (2.6) and the singularity (2.7). Then we look at AI systems as subjects, i.e. when ethics is for the AI systems themselves in machine ethics (2.8.) and artificial moral agency (2.9). Finally we look at future developments and the concept of AI (3). For each section within these themes, we provide a general explanation of the ethical issues, we outline existing positions and arguments, then we analyse how this plays out with current technologies and finally what policy conse-quences may be drawn. '"

  7. Erler, Alexandre and Müller, Vincent C. (2021), 'The ethics of biomedical military research: Therapy, prevention, enhancement, and risk', in Daniel Messelken and David Winkler (eds.), Health care in contexts of risk, uncertainty, and hybridity (Berlin: Springer), 235-52.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: What proper role should considerations of risk, particularly to research subjects, play when it comes to conducting research on human enhancement in the military context? We introduce the currently visible military enhancement techniques (1) and the standard discussion of risk for these (2), in particular what we refer to as the ‘Assumption’, which states that the demands for risk-avoidance are higher for enhancement than for therapy. We challenge the Assumption through the introduction of three categories of enhancements (3): therapeutic, preventive, and pure enhancements. This demands a revision of the Assumption (4), alongside which we propose some further general principles bearing on how to balance risks and benefits in the context of military enhancement research. We identify a particular type of therapeutic enhancements as providing a more responsible path to human trials of the relevant interventions than pure enhancement applications. Finally, we discuss some possible objections to our line of thought (5). While acknowledging their potential insights, we ultimately find them to be unpersuasive, at least provided that our proposal is understood as fully non-coercive towards the candidates for such therapeutic enhancement trials.'"

  8. Müller, Vincent C. (2021), 'Is it time for robot rights? Moral status in artificial entities', Ethics & Information Technology, 23(3), 579–587.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Some authors have recently suggested that it is time to consider rights for robots. These suggestions are based on the claim that the question of robot rights should not depend on a standard set of conditions for ‘moral status’; but instead, the question is to be framed in a new way, by rejecting the is/ought distinction, making a relational turn, or assuming a methodological behaviourism. We try to clarify these suggestions and to show their highly problematic consequences. While we find the suggestions ultimately unmotivated, the discussion shows that our epistemic condition with respect to the moral status of others does raise problems, and that the human tendency to empathise with things that do not have moral status should be taken seriously—we suggest that it produces a “derived moral status”. Finally, it turns out that there is typically no individual in real AI that could even be said to be the bearer of moral status. Overall, there is no reason to think that robot rights are an issue now.

  9. Müller, Vincent C. (2020), 'Ethics of artificial intelligence and robotics', in Edward N. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2020; Palo Alto: CSLI, Stanford University), 1-70.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Artificial intelligence (AI) and robotics are digital technologies that will have significant impact on the development of humanity in the near future. They have raised fundamental questions about what we should do with these systems, what the systems themselves should do, what risks they involve, and how we can control these. - After the Introduction to the field (§1), the main themes (§2) of this article are: Ethical issues that arise with AI systems as objects, i.e., tools made and used by humans. This includes issues of privacy (§2.1) and manipulation (§2.2), opacity (§2.3) and bias (§2.4), human-robot interaction (§2.5), employment (§2.6), and the effects of autonomy (§2.7). Then AI systems as subjects, i.e., ethics for the AI systems themselves in machine ethics (§2.8) and artificial moral agency (§2.9). Finally, the problem of a possible future AI superintelligence leading to a “singularity” (§2.10). We close with a remark on the vision of AI (§3). - For each section within these themes, we provide a general explanation of the ethical issues, outline existing positions and arguments, then analyse how these play out with current technologies and finally, what policy consequences may be drawn.'"

  10. Müller, Vincent C. (2019), 'Measuring progress in robotics: Benchmarking and the ‘measure-target confusion’', in Fabio Bonsignorio, et al. (eds.), Metrics of sensory motor coordination and integration in robots and animals (Cosmos; Berlin: Springer Nature), 169-79.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: While it is often said that robotics should aspire to reproducible and measurable results that allow benchmarking, I argue that a focus on benchmarking can be a hindrance for progress in robotics. The reason is what I call the ‘measure-target confusion’, the confusion between a measure of progress and the target of progress. Progress on a benchmark (the measure) is not identical to scientific or technological progress (the target). In the past, several academic disciplines have been led into pursuing only reproducible and measurable ‘scientific’ results – robotics should be careful to follow that line because results that can be benchmarked must be specific and context-dependent, but robotics targets whole complex systems for a broad variety of contexts. While it is extremely valuable to improve benchmarks to reduce the distance be- tween measure and target, the general problem to measure progress towards more intelligent machines (the target) will not be solved by benchmarks alone; we need a balanced approach with sophisticated benchmarks, plus real-life testing, plus qualitative judgment.'"

  11. Müller, Vincent C. (2018), 'The extended mind thesis is about demarcation and use of words', Reti, saperi, linguaggi: Italian Journal of Cognitive Sciences, 2, 335-48.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: The «extended mind thesis» sounds like a substantive thesis, the truth of which we should investigate. But actually the thesis a) turns about to be just a statement on where the demarcations for the «mental» are to be set (internal, external,…), i.e. it is about the «mark of the mental»; and b) the choice about the mark of the mental is a verbal choice, not a matter of scientific discovery. So, the «extended mind thesis» is a remark on how its supporters or opponents want to use the word ‘mind’, not a thesis of cognitive science or philosophy. The upshot of the extended mind discussion should not be to draw the line further out, but to drop the demarcation project.

  12. Müller, Vincent C. (2018), 'In 30 Schritten zum Mond? Zukünftiger Fortschritt in der KI', Medienkorrespondenz, 20 (05.10.2018), 5-15.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Die Entwicklungen in der Künstlichen Intelligenz (KI) sind spannend. Aber wohin geht die Reise? Ich stelle eine Analyse vor, der zufolge exponentielles Wachstum von Rechengeschwindigkeit und Daten die entscheidenden Faktoren im bisherigen Fortschritt waren. Im Folgenden erläutere ich, unter welchen Annahmen dieses Wachstum auch weiterhin Fortschritt ermöglichen wird: 1) Intelligenz ist eindimensional und messbar, 2) Kognitionswissenschaft wird für KI nicht benötigt, 3) Berechnung (computation) ist hinreichend für Kognition, 4) Gegenwärtige Techniken und Architektur sind ausreichend skalierbar, 5) Technological Readiness Levels (TRL) erweisen sich als machbar. Diese Annahmen werden sich als dubios erweisen.

  13. Müller, Vincent C. and Hoffmann, Matej (2017), 'What is morphological computation? On how the body contributes to cognition and control', Artificial Life 23 (1), 1-24.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: The contribution of the body to cognition and control in natural and artificial agents is increasingly described as “off-loading computation from the brain to the body”, where the body is said to perform “morphological computation”. Our investigation of four characteristic cases of morphological computation in animals and robots shows that the ‘off-loading’ perspective is misleading. Actually, the contribution of body morphology to cognition and control is rarely computational, in any useful sense of the word. We thus distinguish (1) morphology that facilitates control, (2) morphology that facilitates perception and the rare cases of (3) morphological computation proper, such as ‘reservoir computing.’ where the body is actually used for computation. This result contributes to the understanding of the relation between embodiment and computation: The question for robot design and cognitive science is not whether computation is offloaded to the body, but to what extent the body facilitates cognition and control – how it contributes to the overall ‘orchestration’ of intelligent behaviour.

  14. Müller, Vincent C. (2017), 'Legal vs. ethical obligations – a comment on the EPSRC’s principles for robotics', Connection Science, 29 (2), 137-41.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: While the 2010 EPSRC principles for robotics state a set of 5 rules of what ‘should’ be done, I argue they should differentiate between legal obligations and ethical demands. Only if we make this difference can we state clearly what the legal obligations already are, and what additional ethical demands we want to make. I provide suggestions how to revise the rules in this light and how to make them more structured.

  15. Hoffmann, Matej and Müller, Vincent C. (2017), 'Simple or complex bodies? Trade-offs in exploiting body morphology for control', in Gordana Dodig-Crnkovic and Raffaela Giovagnoli (eds.), Representation of Reality: Humans, Other Living Organisms and Intelligent Machines (SAPERE; Berlin: Springer), 335-46.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Engineers fine-tune the design of robot bodies for control purposes, however, a methodology or set of tools is largely absent, and optimization of morphology (shape, material properties of robot bodies, etc.) is lagging behind the development of controllers. This has become even more prominent with the advent of compliant, deformable or ”soft” bodies. These carry substantial potential regarding their exploitation for control—sometimes referred to as ”morphological computation”. In this article, we briefly review different notions of computation by physical systems and propose the dynamical systems framework as the most useful in the context of describing and eventually designing the interactions of controllers and bodies. Then, we look at the pros and cons of simple vs. complex bodies, critically reviewing the attractive notion of ”soft” bodies automatically taking over control tasks. We address another key dimension of the design space—whether model-based control should be used and to what extent it is feasible to develop faithful models for different morphologies.'"

  16. Simpson, Thomas W and Müller, Vincent C. (2016), 'Just war and robots’ killings', The Philosophical Quarterly, 66 (263), 302-22.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: May lethal autonomous weapons systems—‘killer robots’—be used in war? The majority of writers argue against their use, and those who have argued in favour have done so on a consequentialist basis. We defend the moral permissibility of killer robots, but on the basis of the non-aggregative structure of right assumed by Just War theory. This is necessary because the most important argument against killer robots, the responsibility trilemma proposed by Rob Sparrow, makes the same assumptions. We show that the crucial moral question is not one of responsibility. Rather, it is whether the technology can satisfy the requirements of fairness in the re-distribution of risk. Not only is this possible in principle, but some killer robots will actually satisfy these requirements. An implication of our argument is that there is a public responsibility to regulate killer robots’ design and manufacture.

  17. Müller, Vincent C. and Bostrom, Nick (2016), 'Future progress in artificial intelligence: A survey of expert opinion', in Vincent C. Müller (ed.), Fundamental Issues of Artificial Intelligence (Synthese Library; Berlin: Springer), 553-70.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: There is, in some quarters, concern about high–level machine intelligence and superintelligent AI coming up in a few decades, bringing with it significant risks for humanity. In other quarters, these issues are ignored or considered science fiction. We wanted to clarify what the distribution of opinions actually is, what probability the best experts currently assign to high–level machine intelligence coming up within a particular time–frame, which risks they see with that development, and how fast they see these developing. We thus designed a brief questionnaire and distributed it to four groups of experts in 2012/2013. The median estimate of respondents was for a one in two chance that high-level machine intelligence will be developed around 2040-2050, rising to a nine in ten chance by 2075. Experts expect that systems will move on to superintelligence in less than 30 years thereafter. They estimate the chance is about one in three that this development turns out to be ‘bad’ or ‘extremely bad’ for humanity.'"

  18. Müller, Vincent C. (2016), 'New developments in the philosophy of AI', in Vincent C. Müller (ed.), Fundamental Issues of Artificial Intelligence (Synthese Library; Berlin: Springer).
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: The philosophy of AI has seen some changes, in particular: 1) AI moves away from cognitive science, and 2) the long term risks of AI now appear to be a worthy concern. In this context, the classical central concerns – such as the relation of cognition and computation, embodiment, intelligence & rationality, and information – will regain urgency. '"

  19. Müller, Vincent C. (2016), 'Editorial: Risks of artificial intelligence', in Vincent C. Müller (ed.), Risks of artificial intelligence (London: CRC Press - Chapman & Hall), 1-8.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: If the intelligence of artificial systems were to surpass that of humans significantly, this would constitute a significant risk for humanity. Time has come to consider these issues, and this consideration must include progress in AI as much as insights from the theory of AI. The papers in this volume try to make cautious headway in setting the problem, evaluating predictions on the future of AI, proposing ways to ensure that AI systems will be beneficial to humans – and critically evaluating such proposals.'"

  20. Müller, Vincent C. (2016), 'Autonomous killer robots are probably good news', in Ezio Di Nucci and Filippo Santoni de Sio (eds.), Drones and responsibility: Legal, philosophical and socio-technical perspectives on the use of remotely controlled weapons (London: Ashgate), 67-81.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Will future lethal autonomous weapon systems (LAWS), or ‘killer robots’, be a threat to humanity? The European Parliament has called for a moratorium or ban of LAWS; the ‘Contracting Parties to the Geneva Convention at the United Nations’ are presently discussing such a ban, which is supported by the great majority of writers and campaigners on the issue. However, the main arguments in favour of a ban are unsound. LAWS do not support extrajudicial killings, they do not take responsibility away from humans; in fact they increase the abil-ity to hold humans accountable for war crimes. Using LAWS in war would probably reduce human suffering overall. Finally, the availability of LAWS would probably not increase the probability of war or other lethal conflict—especially as compared to extant remote-controlled weapons. The widespread fear of killer robots is unfounded: They are probably good news.'"

  21. Müller, Vincent C. (2015), 'Which symbol grounding problem should we try to solve?', Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence, 27 (1, ed. D. Jones & A. Beavers), 73-78.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Floridi and Taddeo propose a condition of “zero semantic commitment” for solutions to the grounding problem, and a solution to it. I argue briefly that their condition cannot be fulfilled, not even by their own solution. After a look at Luc Steel’s very different competing suggestion, I suggest that we need to re-think what the problem is and what role the ‘goals’ in a system play in formulating the problem. On the basis of a proper (syntactic) understanding of computing, I come to the conclusion that the only sensible grounding problem is how we can explain and re-produce the behavioral ability and function of meaning in artificial computational agents.

  22. Müller, Vincent C. (2015), 'Gun control: A European perspective', Essays in Philosophy, 16 (2), 247-61.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: From a European perspective the US debate about gun control is puzzling because we have no such debate: It seems obvious to us that dangerous weapons need tight control and that ‘guns’ fall under that category. I suggest that this difference occurs due to different habits that generate different attitudes and support this explanation with an analogy to the habits about knives. I conclude that it is plausible that individ-ual knife-people or gun-people do not want tight regulatory legislation – but tight knife and gun legislation is morally obligatory anyway. We need to give up our habits for the greater good.

  23. Müller, Vincent C. (2014), 'Pancomputationalism: Theory or metaphor?', in Ruth Hagengruber and Uwe Riss (eds.), Philosophy, computing and information science (History and philosophy of technoscience; London: Pickering & Chattoo), 213-21.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: The theory that all processes in the universe are computational is attractive in its promise to provide an understandable theory of everything. I want to suggest here that this pancomputationalism is not sufficiently clear on which problem it is trying to solve, and how. I propose two interpretations of pancomputationalism as a theory: I) the world is a computer and II) the world can be described as a computer. The first implies a thesis of supervenience of the physical over computation and is thus reduced ad absurdum. The second is underdetermined by the world, and thus equally unsuccessful as theory. Finally, I suggest that pancomputationalism as metaphor can be useful. – At the Paderborn workshop in 2008, this paper was presented as a commentary to the relevant paper by Gordana Dodig-Crnkovic " Info-Computationalism and Philosophical Aspects of Research in Information Sciences".'"

  24. Müller, Vincent C. (2014), 'Editorial: Risks of general artificial intelligence', Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence, 26 (3 - Special issue ‘Risks of General Artificial Intelligence’, ed. V. Müller), 297-301.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: This is the editorial for a special volume of JETAI, featuring papers by Omohundro, Armstrong/Sotala/O’Heigeartaigh, T Goertzel, Brundage, Yampolskiy, B. Goertzel, Potapov/Rodinov, Kornai and Sandberg. - If the general intelligence of artificial systems were to surpass that of humans significantly, this would constitute a significant risk for humanity – so even if we estimate the probability of this event to be fairly low, it is necessary to think about it now. We need to estimate what progress we can expect, what the impact of superintelligent machines might be, how we might design safe and controllable systems, and whether there are directions of research that should best be avoided or strengthened.

  25. Hoffmann, Matej and Müller, Vincent C. (2014), 'Trade-offs in exploiting body morphology for control: From simple bodies and model-based control to complex ones with model-free distributed control schemes', in Helmut Hauser; Rudolf M Füchslin and Rolf Pfeifer (eds.), Opinions and Outlooks on Morphological Computation (Zurich: E-Book), 185-94.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Tailoring the design of robot bodies for control purposes is implicitly performed by engineers, however, a methodology or set of tools is largely absent and optimization of morphology (shape, material properties of robot bodies, etc.) is lag- ging behind the development of controllers. This has become even more prominent with the advent of compliant, deformable or "soft" bodies. These carry substantial potential regarding their exploitation for control – sometimes referred to as "mor- phological computation" in the sense of offloading computation needed for control to the body. Here, we will argue in favor of a dynamical systems rather than com- putational perspective on the problem. Then, we will look at the pros and cons of simple vs. complex bodies, critically reviewing the attractive notion of “soft” bodies automatically taking over control tasks. We will address another key dimension of the design space – whether model-based control should be used and to what extent it is feasible to develop faithful models for different morphologies. --Müller, Vincent C. This paper was also published in the 2014 AISB proceedings http://aisb50.org/representation-of-reality-humans-animals-and-machines/ - http://doc.gold.ac.uk/aisb50/'"

  26. Müller, Vincent C. (2012), 'Introduction: Theory and Philosophy of Artificial Intelligence', Minds and Machines, 22 (2), 67-69.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: The theory and philosophy of artificial intelligence has come to a crucial point where the agenda for the forthcoming years is in the air. This special volume of Minds and Machines presents leading invited papers from a conference on the “Philosophy and Theory of Artificial Intelligence” that was held in October 2011 in Thessaloniki (www.pt-ai.org). Artificial Intelligence is perhaps unique among engineering subjects in that it has raised very basic questions about the nature of computing, perception, reasoning, learning, language, action, interaction, consciousness, humankind, life etc. etc. – and at the same time it has contributed substantially to answering these questions (in fact, it is sometimes seen as a form of empirical research). There is thus a substantial tradition of work, both on AI by philosophers and of theory within AI itself. - - The volume contains papers by Bostrom, Dreyfus, Gomila, O'Regan and Shagrir. - - This introduction has been re-published (p. VII-IX) in Vincent C. Müller (ed.), Theory and Philosophy of Artificial Intelligence (SAPERE; Berlin: Springer), together with the main volume of papers of PT-AI 2011.

  27. Müller, Vincent C. (2012), 'From embodied and extended mind to no mind', in Anna Esposito, et al. (eds.), Cognitive Behavioural Systems (LNCS/LNAI 7403; Berlin: Springer), 299-303.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: The paper discusses the extended mind thesis with a view to the notions of “agent” and of “mind”, while helping to clarify the relation between “embodiment” and the “extended mind”. I will suggest that the extended mind thesis constitutes a reductio ad absurdum of the notion of ‘mind’; the consequence of the extended mind debate should be to drop the notion of the mind altogether – rather than entering the discussion how extended it is.'"

  28. Gomila, Antoni and Müller, Vincent C. (2012), 'Challenges for artificial cognitive systems', Journal of Cognitive Science, 13 (4), 453-69.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: The declared goal of this paper is to fill this gap: “... cognitive systems research needs questions or challenges that define progress. The challenges are not (yet more) predictions of the future, but a guideline to what are the aims and what would constitute progress.” – the quotation being from the project description of EUCogII, the project for the European Network for Cognitive Systems within which this formulation of the ‘challenges’ was originally developed (http://www.eucognition.org). So, we stick out our neck and formulate the challenges for artificial cognitive systems. These challenges are articulated in terms of a definition of what a cognitive system is: a system that learns from experience and uses its acquired knowledge (both declarative and practical) in a flexible manner to achieve its own goals.

  29. Müller, Vincent C. (2012), 'Autonomous cognitive systems in real-world environments: Less control, more flexibility and better interaction', Cognitive Computation, 4 (3), 212-15.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: In October 2011, the “2nd European Network for Cognitive Systems, Robotics and Interaction”, EUCogII, held its meeting in Groningen on “Autonomous activity in real-world environments”, organized by Tjeerd Andringa and myself. This is a brief personal report on why we thought autonomy in real-world environments is central for cognitive systems research and what I think I learned about it. Müller, Vincent C. The theses that crystallized are that a) autonomy is a relative property and a matter of degree, b) increasing autonomy of an artificial system from its makers and users is a necessary feature of increasingly intelligent systems that can deal with the real-world and c) more such autonomy means less control but at the same time improved interaction with the system.

  30. Müller, Vincent C. (2011), 'On the possibilities of hypercomputing supertasks', Minds and Machines, 21 (1), 83-96.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: This paper investigates the view that digital hypercomputing is a good reason for rejection or re-interpretation of the Church-Turing thesis. After suggestion that such re-interpretation is historically problematic and often involves attack on a straw man (the ‘maximality thesis’), it discusses proposals for digital hypercomputing with “Zeno-machines”, i.e. computing machines that compute an infinite number of computing steps in finite time, thus performing supertasks. It argues that effective computing with Zeno-machines falls into a dilemma: either they are specified such that they do not have output states, or they are specified such that they do have output states, but involve contradiction. Repairs though non-effective methods or special rules for semi-decidable problems are sought, but not found. The paper concludes that hypercomputing supertasks are impossible in the actual world and thus no reason for rejection of the Church-Turing thesis in its traditional interpretation.

  31. Müller, Vincent C. (2011), 'Interaction and resistance: The recognition of intentions in new human-computer interaction', in Anna Esposito, et al. (eds.), Towards autonomous, adaptive, and context-aware multimodal interfaces: Theoretical and practical issues (LNCS, 6456; Berlin: Springer), 1-7.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Just as AI has moved away from classical AI, human-computer interaction (HCI) must move away from what I call ‘good old fashioned HCI’ to ‘new HCI’ – it must become a part of cognitive systems research where HCI is one case of the interaction of intelligent agents (we now know that interaction is essential for intelligent agents anyway). For such interaction, we cannot just ‘analyze the data’, but we must assume intentions in the other, and I suggest these are largely recognized through resistance to carrying out one’s own intentions. This does not require fully cognitive agents but can start at a very basic level. New HCI integrates into cognitive systems research and designs intentional systems that provide resistance to the human agent.'"

  32. Müller, Vincent C. (2011), 'The hard and easy grounding problems (Comment on A. Cangelosi)', International Journal of Signs and Semiotic Systems, 1 (1), 70.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: I see four symbol grounding problems: 1) How can a purely computational mind acquire meaningful symbols? 2) How can we get a computational robot to show the right linguistic behavior? These two are misleading. I suggest an 'easy' and a 'hard' problem: 3) How can we explain and re-produce the behavioral ability and function of meaning in artificial computational agents?4) How does physics give rise to meaning?

  33. Dodig-Crnkovic, Gordana and Müller, Vincent C. (2011), 'A dialogue concerning two world systems: Info-computational vs. mechanistic', in Gordana Dodig-Crnkovic and Mark Burgin (eds.), Information and computation: Essays on scientific and philosophical understanding of foundations of information and computation (Boston: World Scientific), 149-84.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: The dialogue develops arguments for and against a broad new world system - info-computationalist naturalism - that is supposed to overcome the traditional mechanistic view. It would make the older mechanistic view into a special case of the new general info-computationalist framework (rather like Euclidian geometry remains valid inside a broader notion of geometry). We primarily discuss what the info-computational paradigm would mean, especially its pancomputationalist component. This includes the requirements for a the new generalized notion of computing that would include sub-symbolic information processing. We investigate whether pancomputationalism can provide the basic causal structure to the world and whether the overall research program of info-computationalist naturalism appears productive, especially when it comes to new approaches to the living world, including computationalism in the philosophy of mind.'"

  34. Müller, Vincent C. (2010), 'Εικάζει η φιλοσοφία για εμπειρικά δεδομένα; Η γνωσιακή διαπερατότητα της αντίληψης [Does philosophy speculate about empirical facts? The cognitive penetrability of perception]', Noesis - The Journal of the Hellenic Cognitive Science Society, 6 (1), 161-64.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Should we do speculative cognitive science? - In present day philosophy, I see a fashion that uses empirical facts (data) to support positions that are not philosophical but empirical in nature. The argumentative structure is classical philosophy, saying that ‘this has to be that way because …’ where the ‘this’ refers to some empirical state of affairs. This kind of philosophy speculates about empirical facts in areas where we do not yet know the facts – the arguments are a priori, supported by a posteriori data. This is precisely what the speculative philosophy of German Idealism was doing, e.g. in the works of Schelling or Hegel

  35. Müller, Vincent C. (2009), 'Would you mind being watched by machines? Privacy concerns in data mining', AI & Society, 23 (4), 529-44.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Data mining is not an invasion of privacy because access to data is only by machines, not by people: this is the argument that is investigated here. The current importance of this problem is developed in a case study of data mining in the USA for counterterrorism and other surveillance purposes. After a clarification of the relevant nature of privacy, it is argued that access by machines cannot warrant the access to further information, since the analysis will have to be made either by humans or by machines that understand. It concludes that the current data mining violates the right to privacy and should be subject to the standard legal constraints for access to private information by people.

  36. Müller, Vincent C. (2009), 'Symbol grounding in computational systems: A paradox of intentions', Minds and Machines, 19 (4), 529-41.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: The paper presents a paradoxical feature of computational systems that suggests that computationalism cannot explain symbol grounding. If the mind is a digital computer, as computationalism claims, then it can be computing either over meaningful symbols or over meaningless symbols. If it is computing over meaningful symbols its functioning presupposes the existence of meaningful symbols in the system, i.e. it implies semantic nativism. If the mind is computing over meaningless symbols, no intentional cognitive processes are available prior to symbol grounding. In this case, no symbol grounding could take place since any grounding presupposes intentional cognitive processes. So, whether computing in the mind is over meaningless or over meaningful symbols, computationalism implies semantic nativism.

  37. Müller, Vincent C. (2009), 'From public data to private information: The case of the supermarket', in Maria Bottis (ed.), Proceedings of the 8th International Conference Computer Ethics: Philosophical Enquiry (Corfu: Nomiki Bibliothiki), 500-07.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: The background to this paper is that in our world of massively increasing personal digital data any control over the data about me seems illusionary – informational privacy seems a lost cause. On the other hand, the production of this digital data seems a necessary component of our present life in the industrialized world. A framework for a resolution of this apparent dilemma is provided if by the distinction between (meaningless) data and (meaningful) information. I argue that computational data processing is necessary for many present-day processes and not a breach of privacy, while collection and processing of private information is often not necessary and a breach of privacy. The problem and the sketch of its solution are illustrated in a case-study: supermarket customer cards.'"

  38. Müller, Vincent C. (2008), 'Representation in digital systems', in Adam Briggle; Katinka Waelbers and Philip Brey (eds.), Current issues in computing and philosophy (Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence and Applications; Amsterdam: IOS Press), 116-21.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Cognition is commonly taken to be computational manipulation of representations. These representations are assumed to be digital, but it is not usually specified what that means and what relevance it has for the theory. I propose a specification for being a digital state in a digital system, especially a digital computational system. The specification shows that identification of digital states requires functional directedness, either for someone or for the system of which it is a part. In the case or digital representations, to be a token of a representational type, where the function of the type is to represent. [An earlier version of this paper was discussed in the web-conference "Interdisciplines" https://web.archive.org/web/20100221125700/http://www.interdisciplines.org/adaptation/papers/7 ]'"

  39. Müller, Vincent C. (2008), 'Για τη δυνατότητα υπερ-υπολογισμού πέρα από την υπόθεση Church-Turing [On the Possibility of Hypercomputing beyond Church-Turing]', in Dimitra Sfendoni-Mentzou (ed.), Φιλοσοφία τον Επιστιμόν [Philosophy of Science], EFE 2006: Proceedings of the 10th Greek Association for Philosophy Conference (vol. I; Thessaloniki: Zitis), 407-14.
    [Publisher] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Αυτό το άρθρο εξετάζει κατά πόσο ο υπερ-υπολογισμός οδηγεί υποχρεωτικά σε μιαν αναθεώρηση της υπόθεσης Church-Turing. Συζητάει προτάσεις για υπολογιστικές μηχανές, για τις οποίες λέγεται ότι υπολογίζουν άπειρα βήματα υπολογισμού σε πεπερασμένο χρόνο, εκτελώντας «supertasks». Επιχειρηματολογεί ότι αυτές οι προτάσεις οδηγούν στο εξής δίλημμα: είτε δεν περιγράφονται με τέτοιο τρόπο ώστε να έχουν αποτελέσματα, είτε τα αποτελέσματα είναι αντιφατικά. Άρα, ο άπειρος υπερ-υπολογισμός δεν αποτελεί λόγο να απορριφθεί η παραδοσιακή ερμηνεία της υπόθεσης Church-Turing. Η διερεύνηση του υπολογισμού με «supertasks» επίσης υποδεικνύει ότι συγκεκριμένα «supertasks» είναι αδύνατα.'"

  40. Müller, Vincent C. (2007), 'Is there a future for AI without representation?', Minds and Machines, 17 (1), 101-15.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: This paper investigates the prospects of AI without representation in general, and the proposals of Rodney Brooks in particular. What turns out to be characteristic of Brooks proposal is the rejection of central control in intelligent agents; his systems has as much or as little representation as traditional AI. The traditional view that representation is necessary for intelligence pre-supposes that intelligence requires central control. However, much of recent cognitive science suggests that we should dispose of the image of intelligent agents as central representation processors. If this paradigm shift is achieved, Brooks proposal for non-centralized cognition without representation appears promising for full-blown intelligent agents - though not for conscious agents and thus not for human-like AI.

  41. Raftopoulos, Athanassios and Müller, Vincent C. (2006), 'The phenomenal content of experience', Mind and Language, 21 (2), 187-219.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: We discuss at some length evidence from the cognitive science suggesting that the representations of objects based on spatiotemporal information and featural information retrieved bottom-up from a visual scene precede representations of objects that include conceptual information. We argue that a distinction can be drawn between representations with conceptual and nonconceptual content. The distinction is based on perceptual mechanisms that retrieve information in conceptually unmediated ways. The representational contents of the states induced by these mechanisms that are available to a type of awareness called phenomenal awareness constitute the phenomenal content of experience. The phenomenal content of perception contains the existence of objects as separate things that persist in time and time, spatiotemporal information, and information regarding relative spatial relations, motion, surface properties, shape, size, orientation, color, and their functional properties.

  42. Raftopoulos, Athanassios and Müller, Vincent C. (2006), 'Nonconceptual demonstrative reference', Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 72 (2), 251-85.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: The paper argues that the reference of perceptual demonstratives is fixed in a causal nondescriptive way through the nonconceptual content of perception. That content consists first in spatiotemporal information establishing the existence of a separate persistent object retrieved from a visual scene by the perceptual object segmentation processes that open an object-file for that object. Nonconceptual content also consists in other transducable information, that is, information that is retrieved directly in a bottom-up way from the scene (motion, shape, etc). The nonconceptual content of the mental states induced when one uses a perceptual demonstrative constitutes the mode of presentation of the perceptual demonstrative that individuates but does not identify the object of perceptual awareness and allows reference to it. On that account, perceptual demonstratives put us in a de re relationship with objects in the world through the non-conceptual information retrieved directly from the objects in the environment.

  43. Müller, Vincent C. (2006), 'Some information is too dangerous to be on the Internet', Computers and Society, 36 (1), 1-11.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: This paper investigates a problem about freedom of information. Although freedom of information is generally considered desirable, there are a number of areas where there is substantial agreement that freedom of information should be limited. After a certain ordering of the landscape, I argue that we need to add the category of "dangerous" information and that this category has gained a new quality in the context of current information technology, specifically the Internet. This category includes information the use of which would be morally wrong as well as some of what may be called "corrupting" information. Some such information should not be spread at all and some should be very limited in its spread.

  44. Müller, Vincent C. (2005), 'There must be encapsulated nonconceptual content in vision', in Athanassios Raftopoulos (ed.), Cognitive penetrability of perception: Attention, action, attention and bottom-up constraints (Huntington: Nova Science), 157-70.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: In this paper I want to propose an argument to support Jerry Fodor’s thesis (Fodor 1983) that input systems are modular and thus informationally encapsulated. The argument starts with the suggestion that there is a “grounding problem” in perception, i. e. that there is a problem in explaining how perception that can yield a visual experience is possible, how sensation can become meaningful perception of something for the subject. Given that visual experience is actually possible, this invites a transcendental argument that explains the conditions of its possibility. I propose that one of these conditions is the existence of a visual module in Fodor’s sense that allows the step from sensation to object-identifying perception, thus enabling visual experience. It seems to follow that there is informationally encapsulated nonconceptual content in visual perception.'"

  45. Müller, Vincent C. (2002), 'Communicating the same information to a human and to a machine: Is there a difference in principle?', in Konstantinos Boudouris and Takis Poulakos (eds.), Philosophy of communication: Proceedings of the 13th international conference on Greek philosophy (IAGP 13) (2; Athens: Ionia), 168-76.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: We try to show that there is no difference in principle between communicating a piece of information to a human and to a machine. The argumentation depends on the following theses: Communicating is transfer of information; information has propositional form; propositional form can be modelled as categorization; categorisation can be modelled in a machine; a suitably equipped machine can grasp propositional content designed for human communication. What I suggest is that the discussion should focus on the truth and precise meaning of these statements. However, in case these statements are true it follows that: For any act of communication that suc-cessfully transfers a piece of information to a human, that act could also transfer that piece of information to a machine.'"

  46. Raftopoulos, Athanassios and Müller, Vincent C. (2002), 'Deictic codes, demonstratives, and reference: A step toward solving the grounding problem', in Wayne D. Gray and Christian D. Schunn (eds.), CogSci 2002, 24th annual meeting of the Cognitive Science Society (Mahwah, NY: Lawrence Erlbaum), 762-67.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: In this paper we address the issue of grounding for experiential concepts. Given that perceptual demonstratives are a basic form of such concepts, we examine ways of fixing the referents of such demonstratives. To avoid ‘encodingism’, that is, relating representations to representations, we postulate that the process of reference fixing must be bottom-up and nonconceptual, so that it can break the circle of conceptual content and touch the world. For that purpose, an appropriate causal relation between representations and the world is needed. We claim that this relation is provided by spatial and object-centered attention that leads to the formation of object files through the function of deictic acts. This entire causal process takes place at a pre-conceptual level, meeting the requirement for a solution to the grounding problem. Finally we claim that our account captures fundamental insights in Putnam’s and Kripke’s work on “new” reference.'"

  47. Müller, Vincent C. (2000), 'How do we read a dictionary (as machines and as humans)? Kinds of information in dictionaries constructed and reconstructed', in Evangelos Dermatas (ed.), Proceedings of COMLEX2000: Computational lexicography (WCL; Patras: Patras University Press), 141-44.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Two large lexicological projects for the Center for the Greek Language, Thessaloniki, were to be published in print and on the WWW, which meant that two conversions were needed: a near-database file had to be converted to fully formatted file for printing and a fully formatted file had to be converted to a database for WWW access. As it turned out, both conversions could make use of existing clues that indicated the kinds of information contained in each particular piece of text, thus separating fields from each other and ordering them into a tree-like structure. This indicates that both forms of the dictionaries, print and database, stem from the same cognitive need to categorize information into a kind of information before further understanding – be this for a human reader or for a machine.'"

  48. Müller, Vincent C. and Kelter, Stephanie (1998), 'Too much substance – not enough cognition. Commentary on Ruth Millikan: “A common structure for concepts of individuals, stuffs and real kinds”', Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 21 (1), 80-81.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Millikan’s account of substance concepts is based on a notion of “substance” expanded from realist notions of individuals and natural kinds. Her metaphysical notion, based on “inductive potential,” is shown to be too puristic and needs to incorporate cognizing subjects. This could preserve the realist/nondescriptionist insight that the extension of sub- stances is determined by the world.

  49. Müller, Vincent C. (1997), 'Real vagueness', in Georg Meggle (ed.), Analyomen 2: Perspectives in analytical philosophy (II: Philosophy of Language; Metaphysics; Berlin: de Gruyter), 398-403.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: The nature of vagueness is investigated via a preliminary definition and a discussion of the classical sorites paradox ; this is carried further by asking for the origins of vagueness and a critique of several attempts to remove it from language. It is shown that such attempts are ill motivated and doomed for failure since vagueness is not just a matter of ignorance but firmly grounded in epistemic and metaphysical facts. Finally, the philosophical interest of real vagueness is illustrated by the concept of “natural kind”, which is essential to realism/anti-realism debates.'"

  50. Müller, Vincent C. and Stein, Christian (1996), 'Epistemic theories of truth: The justifiability paradox investigated', in C. Martínez Vidal; U. Rivas Monroy and L. Villegas Forero (eds.), Verdad: Lógica, Representatión y Mundo (Santiago de Compostela: Universidade de Santiago de Compostela), 95-104.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Epistemic theories of truth, such as those presumed to be typical for anti-realism, can be characterised as saying that what is true can be known in principle: p → ◊Kp. However, with statements of the form “p & ¬Kp”, a contradiction arises if they are both true and known. Analysis of the nature of the paradox shows that such statements refute epistem- ic theories of truth only if the the anti-realist motivation for epistemic theories of truth is not taken into account. The motivation in a link of understandability and meaningful- ness suggests to change the above principle and to restrict the theory to logically simple sentences, in which case the paradox does not arise. This suggestion also allows to see the deep philosophical problems for anti-realism those counterexamples are pointing at.'"

  51. Müller, Vincent C. (1993), 'Einleitung [Introduction]', in Vincent C. Müller (ed.), Hilary Putnam: Von einem realistischen Standpunkt, Schriften zu Sprache und Wirklichkeit [From a realist point of view: Writings on language and reality] (rowohlts enzyklopädie; Reinbek: Rowohlt), 9-26.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Hilary Putnams Biographie und philosophische Entwicklung spiegeln die Geschichte der angelsächsischen Philosophie in den letzten 40 Jahren. Beinahe ebenso lange hat Putnam diese Geschichte wesentlich beeinflußt und so kann John Passmore über Putnam schreiben: «Er ist die Geschichte der gegenwärtigen Philosophie im Umriß»1. In der vorliegenden Einleitung soll vor allem der Kontext dargestellt werden, in dem Putnam steht und aus dem heraus verständlich wird, was er philosophisch zu sagen hat. Dieser Kontext ist sicherlich ein Grund dafür, daß Putnam hierzulande noch relativ wenig bekannt ist, während er in den USA häufig für den bedeutendsten aktiven Philosophen gehalten wird. Im Rahmen einer Skizze von Putnams philosophischer Entwicklung soll zudem eine vorläufige philosophiehistorische Einordnung versucht werden, auch wenn hier nicht der Ort für eine umfassende Kritik oder Darstellung sein kann: Die Einleitung muß auf recht elementarem Niveau bleiben und kann eine Lektüre der Texte natürlich nicht ersetzen. Da Putnams Werk sicherlich Teil einer Annäherung von ‹analytischer› und ‹kontinentaler› Philosophie ist, soll bei der Einführung in die hier übersetzten Texte schließlich deutlich werden, was Putnam nicht analytisch orientierten Lesern zu bieten hat. '"

Academic Theses

  1. Müller, Vincent C. (1999), Realismus und Referenz: Arten von Arten [Realism and Reference: Kinds of Kinds] (Fachbereich Philosophie und Sozialwissenschaften, Dr. phil.; Hamburg: Universität Hamburg)
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Die gegenwärtig unter dem Titel ›Realismus‹ geführten Debatten in der Philosophie befinden sich nach allgemeiner Ansicht in einem Zustand größter Verwirrung, so daß es nützlich erscheint, ein wenig Ordnung in die theoretischen Optionen zu bringen bevor man für die eine oder andere Auffassung Partei ergreift. In der vorliegenden Arbeit wird dafür argumentiert, daß sich ein systematisch zusammenhängendes Zentrum dieser Debatten mit Hilfe des Begriffes der Referenz ordnen läßt. Nach der Analyse einiger klassischer Positionen soll ein Rahmen erstellt werden, innerhalb dessen die Positionen eingeordnet und die zentralen Probleme fruchtbar diskutiert werden können. Zu diesem Zwecke ist es erforderlich, für die Einordnung der Positionen theoretische Kriterien zu benennen, die sich an den Problemen orientieren von denen hier argumentiert wird, das sie zentral seien. Sehr knapp ausgedrückt wird hier die Auffassung vertreten, Realismus sei als metaphysische These aufzufassen, welche eine von menschlichen epistemischen und semantischen Möglichkeiten unabhängige Existenz behauptet; in den gegenwärtigen Debatten typischerweise die Existenz einer Art von Dingen, nicht die eines individuellen Gegenstandes. Diese metaphysische These wird jedoch in der gegenwärtigen Debatte mit semantischen Argumenten untermauert, bzw. angegriffen und jene semantischen Argumente wiederum verwenden epistemische Erwägungen – die Frage betreffend, was man wissen kann und was nicht. Der Beginn der gegenwärtigen Realismusdebatten mit der soeben skizzierten zentralen Stellung semantischer Argumente ist, der hier vertretenen Auffassung zufolge, die Kritik am traditionellen Fregeschen Referenzbegriff durch Kripke und den frühen Putnam um 1970 (Kap. 2). Aus dieser neu zu bewertenden Kritik und der von den Autoren daraus entwickelten externalistischen realistischen Semantik für Artausdrücke läßt sich das erste Kriterium für eine Position in einer Realismusdebatte ableiten und klären (Kap. 3): Hält man die fragliche Art für eine natürliche Art und meint also, sie habe ihren ›Zusammenhalt‹ von Natur aus? Wenn ja, dann ist die fragliche Position eine realistische (das Kriterium ist dank des engen Zusammenhangs von Realismus und Externalismus sowohl hinreichend als auch notwendig). Hält man die Art nicht für eine natürliche Art, ist man Antirealist. Damit geht jeweils not- wendig eine bestimmte Semantik für den auf die Art referierenden Ausdruck einher. Es zeigt sich zugleich, daß es zwei Varianten des Realismus zu unterscheiden gilt, die hier als klassischer bzw. als moderater Realismus bezeichnet werden. Im folgenden (Kap. 4.1) wird argumentiert, daß der Begriff der Wahrheit nicht eigentlich der zentrale Punkt in den in Frage stehenden Realismusdebatten sein sollte, wie vielfach behauptet wurde, sondern seine Brisanz vielmehr aus zugrundeliegenden semantischen Fragen gewinnt die also in der weiteren Aufdeckung der Kriterien die zentrale Rolle spielen müssen. In der Analyse der Kritik an der in Kap. 3 entwickelten Position des ›klassischen Realismus‹ läßt sich ein zweites unterscheidendes Kriterium für Positionen in Realismusdebatten entwickeln: begriffliche Relativität. Nach der Ablehnung von Putnams Auffassungen zu diesem Thema, werden zwei Varianten vorgeschlagen, starke und schwache begriffliche Relativität (Kap. 4.2). Die Anwendung dieses Merkmals zwingt, so wird argumentiert, in einigen Fällen zu einer Kombination einer realistischen Auffassung von Arten als natürliche mit begrifflicher Relativität. Diese mittlere Position zwischen klassischem Realismus und Antirealismus wird als »moderater Realismus« bezeichnet. Der im ersten Kriterium verwendete Begriff der natürlichen Art, und damit die Optionen in den Debatten, wird schließlich mittels einer Dis- kussion des Phänomens der Vagheit noch weiter verdeutlicht (Kap. 4.3). Ab- schließend werden die drei Optionen zusammenfassend dargestellt und ein Versuch unternommen, ihre Fruchtbarkeit für diverse Realismusdebatten anzudeuten.'"

Miscellaneous Academic Work: Reviews, Translations, Reports, Bibliography, Papers in Proceedings

  1. McDermid, John; Müller, Vincent C.; Pipe, Tony; Porter, Zoe and Winfield, Alan (2019), 'Ethical issues for robotics and autonomous systems', UK-RAS, UK Robotics and Autonomous Systems Network, 1-18.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: There are unusual challenges in ethics for RAS. Perhaps the issue can best be summarised as needing to consider “technically informed ethics”. The technology of RAS raises issues that have an ethical dimension, and perhaps uniquely so due to the possibility of moving human decision-making which is implicitly ethically informed to computer systems. Further, if seeking solutions to these problems – ethically aligned design, to use the IEEE’s terminology – then the solutions must be technically meaningful, capable of realisation, capable of assurance, and suitable as a basis for regulation. Thus, ethics for RAS is a rich, complex multi-disciplinary concern, and perhaps more complex than many other ethical issues facing society today. It is also fast-moving. This paper has endeavoured to give an accessible introduction to some of the key issues, noting that many of them are quite subtle, and it is not possible to do them full justice in such a short document. However, we have sought to counterbalance this by giving an extensive list of initiatives, standards, etc. that focus on ethics of RAS and AI, see Annex A.

  2. Müller, Vincent C. and Bostrom, Nick (2014), 'Future progress in artificial intelligence: A poll among experts', AI Matters, 1 (1), 9-11.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: [This is the short version of: Müller, Vincent C. and Bostrom, Nick (forthcoming 2016), ‘Future progress in artificial intelligence: A survey of expert opinion’, in Vincent C. Müller (ed.), Fundamental Issues of Artificial Intelligence (Synthese Library 377; Berlin: Springer).] - - - In some quarters, there is intense concern about high–level machine intelligence and superintelligent AI coming up in a few dec- ades, bringing with it significant risks for human- ity; in other quarters, these issues are ignored or considered science fiction. We wanted to clarify what the distribution of opinions actually is, what probability the best experts currently assign to high–level machine intelligence coming up within a particular time–frame, which risks they see with that development and how fast they see these developing. We thus designed a brief questionnaire and distributed it to four groups of experts. Overall, the results show an agreement among experts that AI systems will probably reach overall human ability around 2040-2050 and move on to superintelligence in less than 30 years thereafter. The experts say the probability is about one in three that this development turns out to be ‘bad’ or ‘extremely bad’ for humanity.

  3. Müller, Vincent C. and Simpson, Thomas W (2014), 'Killer robots: Regulate, don’t ban', University of Oxford, Blavatnik School of Government Policy Memo, November 2014, 1-4.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Lethal Autonomous Weapon Systems (‘LAWS’) are here. Technological development will see them become widespread in the near future. This is in a matter of years rather than decades. When the UN Convention on Certain Conventional Weapons meets on 10-14th November 2014, well-considered guidance for a decision on the general policy direction for LAWS is clearly needed. While there is widespread opposition to LAWS—or ‘killer robots’, as they are popularly called—and a growing campaign advocates banning them outright, we argue the opposite. LAWS may very well reduce suffering and death in war. Rather than banning them, they should be regulated, to ensure both compliance with international humanitarian law, and that this positive outcome occurs. This policy memo sets out the basic structure and content of the regulation required.

  4. Müller, Vincent C. (2013), '20 years after The Embodied Mind - why is cognitivism alive and kicking?', in Joel Parthmore and Blay Whitby (eds.), Re-Conceptualizing Mental "Illness": The View from Enactivist Philosophy and Cognitive Science - AISB Convention 2013 (Hove: AISB), 47-49.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: I want to suggest that the major influence of classical arguments for embodiment like "The Embodied Mind" by Varela, Thomson & Rosch (1991) has been a changing of positions rather than a refutation: Cognitivism has found ways to retreat and regroup at positions that have better fortification, especially when it concerns theses about artificial intelligence or artificial cognitive systems. For example: a) Agent-based cognitivism' that understands humans as taking in representations of the world, doing rule-based processing and then acting on them (sense-plan-act) is often limited to conscious decision processes; and b) Purely syntactic cognition is compatible with embodiment, or supplemented by embodiment (e.g. for 'grounding'). While the empirical thesis of embodied cognition ('embodied cognitive science') is true and the practical engineering thesis ('morphological computation', 'cheap design') is often true, the conceptual thesis ('embodiment is necessary for cognition') is likely false - syntax is often enough for cognition, unless grounding is really necessary. I conclude that it has become more sensible to integrate embodiment with traditional approaches rather than "fight for embodiment" or "against cognitivism".'"

  5. Müller, Vincent C. (2013), 'What is a digital state?', in Mark J. Bishop and Yasemin J. Erden (eds.), The Scandal of Computation - What is Computation? - AISB Convention 2013 (Hove: AISB), 11-16.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: There is much discussion about whether the human mind is a computer, whether the human brain could be emulated on a computer, and whether at all physical entities are computers (pancomputationalism). These discussions, and others, require criteria for what is digital. I propose that a state is digital if and only if it is a token of a type that serves a particular function - typically a representational function for the system. This proposal is made on a syntactic level, assuming three levels of description (physical, syntactic, semantic). It suggests that being digital is a matter of discovery or rather a matter of how we wish to describe the world, if a functional description can be assumed. Given the criterion provided and the necessary empirical research, we should be in a position to decide on a given system (e.g. the human brain) whether it is a digital system and can thus be reproduced in a different digital system (since digital systems allow multiple realization).'"

  6. Müller, Vincent C. (2011), 'Philosophy and Theory of Artificial Intelligence, 3–4 October (Report on PT-AI 2011)', The Reasoner, 5 (11), 192-93.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Report for "The Reasoner" on the conference "Philosophy and Theory of Artificial Intelligence", 3 & 4 October 2011, Thessaloniki, Anatolia College/ACT, http://www.pt-ai.org. Müller, Vincent C. Organization: Vincent C. Müller, Professor of Philosophy at ACT & James Martin Fellow, Oxford http://www.sophia.de Müller, Vincent C. Sponsors: EUCogII, Oxford-FutureTech, AAAI, ACM-SIGART, IACAP, ECCAI

  7. Müller, Vincent C. (2009), 'Review of Susan Stuart & Gordana Dodig Crnkovic (eds.): 'Computation, Information, Cognition: The Nexus and the Liminal' (Newcastle: Cambridge Scholars Publishing, 2007)', Cybernetics & Human Knowing, 16 (3-4), 201-03.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Review of: "Computation, Information, Cognition: The Nexus and the Liminal", Ed. Susan Stuart & Gordana Dodig Crnkovic, Newcastle: Cambridge Scholars Publishing, September 2007, xxiv+340pp, ISBN: 9781847180902, Hardback: £39.99, $79.99 -Müller, Vincent C. Are you a computer? Is your cat a computer? A single biological cell in your stomach, perhaps? And your desk? You do not think so? Well, the authors of this book suggest that you think again. They propose a computational turn, a turn towards computational explanation and towards the explanation of computation itself. The explanation of computation is the core of the present volume, but the computational turn to regard a wide variety of systems as computational is a potentially very wide-ranging project.

  8. Müller, Vincent C. (2008), 'Margaret Boden 'Mind as Machine: A History of Cognitive Science' (2 vols., Oxford University Press 2006)', Minds and Machines, 18 (1), 121-25.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Review of: Margaret A. Boden, Mind as Machine: A History of Cognitive Science, 2 vols, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006, xlvii+1631, cloth $225, ISBN 0-19-924144-9. - Mind as Machine is Margaret Boden’s opus magnum. For one thing, it comes in two massive volumes of nearly 1700 pages, ... But it is not just the opus magnum in simple terms of size, but also a truly crowning achievement of half a century’s career in cognitive science.

  9. Müller, Vincent C. (2008), 'What a course on philosophy of computing is not', APA Newsletter on Philosophy and Computers, 8 (1), 36-38.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Immanuel Kant famously defined philosophy to be about three questions: “What can I know? What should I do? What can I hope for?” (KrV, B833). I want to suggest that the three questions of our course on the philosophy of computing are: What is computing? What should we do with computing? What could computing do?

  10. Müller, Vincent C. (2006), 'Πενήντα χρόνια τεχνητής νοημοσύνης: γιατί δεν επιτύχαμε ακόμα; [Fifty years of artificial intelligence: Why have we not succeeded yet?]', Cogito, 4, 48-49. Reprint: (short version) Angeliofóros newspaper, 26.02.2006, p. 38
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: 1 Οι Αρχές - 2 Η δοκιμασία του Turing - 3 Η κλασική τεχνητή νοημοσύνη - 4 Η τεχνητή νοημοσύνη σήμερα - 5 Η τεχνητή νοημοσύνη του μέλλοντος - Με τις τεχνολογίες του παρόντος μάλλον θα δυσκολευτούμε να φτάσουμε στην κατασκευή μηχανών με τεχνητή νοημοσύνη. Κατά την γνώμη μου, θα δούμε άλλες τεχνικές λύσεις με την κλασική τεχνητή νοημοσύνη και μέθοδο «από κάτω προς τα πάνω», αλλά δεν περιμένω να υπάρξει ριζοσπαστική πρόοδος πριν μάθουμε πολλά παραπάνω για τον εγκέφαλό μας. Υπάρχουν πολύ καλοί λόγοι για να λέμε ότι το μυαλό μας δεν είναι υπολογιστής και δεν περιμένω να μπορούμε να φτιάχνουμε νόηση μόνο με υπολογιστή. Αλλά θα μπορούσαμε με άλλα μηχανήματα, γιατί όχι;

  11. Müller, Vincent C. (2005), 'Τι είναι η πατρίδα μας; [What is our fatherland?]', Cogito, 3, 8-10.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Ποια είναι η πατρίδα κάποιων; Ας δούμε το θέμα λίγο σαν πρόβλημα της φιλοσοφίας της γλώσσας: για ένα κατηγόρημα «Άγγλος» «Γάλλος», «Πορτογάλος», «Βέλγος», «Φλαμανδός», πώς να αποφασίσουμε ποια αντικείμενα (ποιοι άνθρωποι) εμπίπτουν σε ποιο κατηγόρημα; Έχουν τελικά νόημα αυτά τα κατηγορήματα; Η χρήση και κατάχρηση αυτών των κατηγορημάτων έχει αποτελέσει μια από τις κυριότερες πηγές δυστυχίας στη διάρκεια των δύο τελευταίων αιώνων και συνεχίζει να είναι στην ημερήσια διάταξη. Συνήθως εμφανίζεται στα πλαίσια αγώνων για την απόκτηση «ελευθερίας» σε αντιπαράθεση με την «καταπίεση», και σε παγκόσμιο επίπεδο και κοντύτερα μας: στη Μακεδονία, την Καταλονία, την Ιρλανδία, το Κουρδιστάν ... Νομίζω πώς αρκετά από αυτά βασίζονται σε λάθη.

  12. Müller, Vincent C. (2004), '“Der Mann mit Eigenschaften”, review of Joseph LeDoux: Im Netz der Persönlichkeit: Wie unser Selbst entsteht [Synaptic Self], Düsseldorf: Walter Verlag 2003', Süddeutsche Zeitung, (14.01.2004), 14.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Review of Joseph LeDoux: Das Netz der Persönlichkeit. Wie unser Selbst entsteht. Walter Verlag, Düsseldorf 2003. 510 Seiten (mit Abbildungen), 39,90 Euro. - Der eine Mensch ist mißtrauisch, der nächste leichtgläubig, diese ist warmherzig, jene kaltschnäuzig. Viele haben Charakter, manche sogar Persönlichkeit. Wie kommt es dazu? In seinem neuen Buch untersucht der Neurowissenschaftler Joseph LeDoux wie unser Selbst entsteht. In dem sehr lesbaren und angenehm übersetzten Werk wird anschaulich und detailliert berichtet, wie sich in unserem Gehirn die Charakteristika eines Individuums ausbilden.

  13. Sainsbury, Richard Mark (2001), Paradoxien, trans. Vincent C. Müller (2nd, revised edn., Universal-Bibliothek, 18135; Stuttgart: Reclam).
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Translation of "Mark Sainsbury: Paradoxes. Cambridge University Press, 2nd edition 1995" into German'"

  14. Adams, Robert Merrihew (1998), 'Mittleres Wissen und das Problem des Übels [Middle knowledge and the problem of evil]', trans. Vincent C. Müller, in Christoph Jäger (ed.), Analytische Religionsphilosophie (UTB; Berlin: Ferdinand Schöningh), 253-72.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Wenn Präsident Kennedy nicht erschossen worden wäre, hätte er dann Nordvietnam bombardiert? Das weiß Gott allein. Oder doch nicht? Weiß wenigstens Er, was Kennedy getan hätte? ... Die Jesuiten behaupteten unter anderem, daß viele menschliche Handlungen in dem Sinne frei seien, daß die Ausführenden nicht logisch oder kausal gezwungen seien, sie auszuführen. („Frei“ wird im vorliegenden Aufsatz stets in diesem Sinne verwendet werden.) Wie behält Gott dann die Kontrolle über die menschliche Geschichte? Nicht dadurch, daß Er menschliche Handlungen kausal determiniert, wie die Dominikaner geglaubt zu haben scheinen , sondern indem Er Umstände herbeiführt, von denen Er weiß, daß wir in ihnen freiwillig Seinen Plänen entsprechend handeln werden. '"

  15. Pike, Nelson (1998), 'Hume über Übel [Hume on evil]', trans. Vincent C. Müller, in Christoph Jäger (ed.), Analytische Religionsphilosophie (UTB; Berlin: Ferdinand Schöningh), 227-44.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: In den Abschnitten X und XI der Dialoge über Natürliche Religion legt Hume seine Ansichten zum traditionellen theologischen Problem des Übels dar. Humes Anmerkungen zu diesem Thema scheinen mir eine reichhaltige Mischung aus Einsichten und Irrtümern zu enthalten. Mein Ziel in diesem Aufsatz besteht darin, diese entgegengesetzten Elemente seiner Diskussion zu entwirren'"

  16. Quinn, Philip L. (1998), 'Auf der Suche nach den Fundamenten des Theismus [In Search of the Foundations of Theism]', trans. Vincent C. Müller, in Christoph Jäger (ed.), Analytische Religionsphilosophie (UTB; Berlin: Ferdinand Schöningh), 331-53.
    [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Dieser Aufsatz ist eine kritische und erkundende Diskussion von Plantingas Behauptung, daß bestimmte Aussagen, aus denen evidentermaßen folgt, daß Gott existiert, berechtigterweise basal sein könnten. Im kritischen Abschnitt argumentiere ich dafür, daß es Plantinga nicht gelingt zu zeigen, daß das Kriterium des modernen Fundamentalisten für berechtigte Basalität, dem zufolge solche Aussagen nicht berechtigterweise basal sein können, selbstreferentiell inkohärent oder anderweitig mangelhaft ist. Im erkundenden Abschnitt versuche ich, ein Argument für die Auffassung zu entwickeln, daß solche Aussagen, selbst wenn sie berechtigterweise basal sein könnten, wenn überhaupt, nur selten berechtigterweise basal für intellektuell differenzierte erwachsene Theisten unserer Kultur wären.'"

  17. Schlesinger, George N. (1998), 'Leid und Übel [Suffering and evil]', trans. Vincent C. Müller, in Christoph Jäger (ed.), Analytische Religionsphilosophie (UTB; Berlin: Ferdinand Schöningh), 245-52.
    [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Die Welt ist voller Leid. Gott ist entweder unfähig, es zu verhindern – dann ist Er nicht allmächtig –, oder Er will es nicht verhindern – dann ist Er nicht vollkommen gut. Seit Generationen wird dies als das schlagendste Argument gegen den Glauben angesehen, daß ein allmächtiges und allgütiges Wesen existiert. Natürlich haben Theisten sich die größte Mühe gegeben, eine angemessene Erwiderung vorzubringen. ... Selbst wenn nur ein einziges Individuum unnötigerweise für einen kurzen Moment eine leichte Unannehmlichkeit zu ertragen hätte, wäre das Problem logisch ebenso real – obwohl es nicht so schmerzhaft wäre oder möglicherweise sogar unbemerkt bliebe'"

  18. Müller, Vincent C. (1996), 'Review of Crispin Wright "Truth and Objectivity" (Harvard University Press 1993)', Erkenntnis, 44 (1), 119-23.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: This book is a new attempt to clarify what is at issue in the contemporary realism debates and to suggest which form the controversies ought to take. Wright has contributed to the-se debates for quite some time and essentially taken the anti-realist side (witness the papers collected in Realism, Meaning and Truth, 1987, 21993, and the forthcoming Realism, Rules and Objectivity, both Oxford: Basil Blackwell). In Truth and Objectivity however, he takes a step back and sketches a neutral ground upon which both sides could agree in or-der to define their oppositions clearly, thus enabling fruitful discussions. His methodolog-ical suggestion for a realism debate in a given assertoric discourse is that both sides should agree on a “minimal” concept of truth for that discourse and then see whether ascent to a more metaphysically substantial concept of truth is warranted, which would constitute a realism for the discourse in question. If Wright had managed to set the agenda in a way that does justice to both sides, this book would have constituted a major contribution to contemporary epistemology and metaphysics.

  19. Müller, Vincent C. (1994), 'Review of Mark Sainsbury, Paradoxes (Cambridge University Press, 1988)', in Gianfranco Soldati (ed.), European Review of Philosophy 1: Philosophy of Mind (Stanford: CSLI Publications), 182-84.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Review of Mark Sainsbury, Paradoxes (Cambridge University Press, 1988)'"

  20. Müller, Vincent C. (1993), 'Bibliographie der Schriften von Hilary Putnam [Bibliography of Hilary Putnam's Writings]', in Vincent C. Müller (ed.), Hilary Putnam: Von einem realistischen Standpunkt, Schriften zu Sprache und Wirklichkeit [From a realist point of view: Writings on language and reality] (rowohlts enzyklopädie; Reinbek: Rowohlt), 278-94. Reprint: Reprinted in Hilary Putnam: Pragmatism: An Open Question, Oxford: Blackwell 1995, 82–102.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Bibliography of the writings by Hilary Putnam: 16 books, 198 articles, 10 translations into German (up to 1994)'"

  21. Sainsbury, Richard Mark (1993), Paradoxien, trans. Vincent C. Müller (Universal-Bibliothek, 8881; Stuttgart: Reclam).
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Translation of "Mark Sainsbury: Paradoxes. Cambridge University Press 1989" into German'"

Journalism & Interviews

    [very incomplete]

  1. Linß, Vera and Müller, Vincent C. (2022), 'Warum der Mensch-Maschine-Vergleich hinkt', Deutschlandfunk, 07.07.2022, 27:31.
    [Publisher] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Was unterscheidet den Menschen von der Maschine? Mit der Weiterentwicklung Künstlicher Intelligenz stellt sich diese Frage immer wieder neu, auch in Bezug auf Bewusstsein und Gefühle. Das schürt bei manchen Ängste. Zu Recht?

  2. Müller, Vincent C.; Bastian, Matthias and Schreiner, Maximilian (2022), 'Podcast DEEP MINDS #3 – KI & Technikphilosophie – Vincent C. Müller', Mixed Podcast.
    [Publisher] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Mit Vincent haben wir über Künstliche Intelligenz und Technikphilosophie gesprochen und über Themen wie: Wie verändert der KI-Boom die Arbeit eines Technikphilosophen? Was ist Intelligenz und kann eine Maschine intelligent sein – sogar schon eine Wenn-Dann-Schleife? Was ist eigentlich Denken? Wann akzeptieren Menschen Roboter als Fahrer? Was sind ethische und gesellschaftliche Herausforderungen bei Künstlicher Intelligenz?

  3. vpro Tegenlicht and Müller, Vincent C. (2021), 'De digimens (the digital human)', NPO2, 07.11.2021, 22:05 (esp. 0:32ff).
    [Publisher] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Can you imagine discussing your problems with a digital therapist instead of a real person? Virtual assistants are on the rise and are getting better at empathy and emotion. Will we soon see or hear the difference between humans and machines? - Perhaps these digital people can help us solve structural problems such as staff shortages in healthcare and education. The question is whether we should want that. VPRO Tegenlicht speaks to a number of pioneers in the area of the digital world.

  4. Müller, Vincent C. and Jónsson, Stefán (2021), 'Podcast: Vincent C. Müller, Ethics in Technology and AI', UT hlaðvarp Ský, Iceland, 06.06.2021.
    [Publisher] [Abstract]
    Abstract: In this episode we talk to Vincent Müller, professor in Ethics of Technology at the Technical University of Eindhoven. At the speed technology is evolving, one can not be surprised that many ethical dilemmas arise. We try to give an overview of what we consider some of the biggest dilemmas to give a feeling for the landscape of ethics of technology and AI. We talk about privacy and data collection, responsibility of AI, autonomy, deepfakes and the future of AI among other things.

  5. Müller, Vincent C. and Fagella, Dan (2016), 'Is Embodied Intelligence a Necessity for Flexible, Adaptive Thinking? – A Conversation ', TechEmergence Podcasts (#149), 15.05.2016.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: What is intelligence? For some researchers, it may be quite possible to create an intelligent machine ‘in a box’, something without physical embodiment but with a powerful mind. Others believe general intelligence requires interaction with the outside world, inferring information from gestures and other features of functioning in an environment. Dr. Vincent Müller is of the belief that intelligence may involve more than just mental algorithms and may need to include the capacity to sense rather than just run a program. Vincent focuses on cognitive systems as an approach to AI, and in this episode he talks about what this means and implies, how this approach is different from classical AI, and what this might permit in the future if the field is developed.

  6. Müller, Vincent C. and Mazur, Susan (2013), 'Robots and the 1% – Interview by Suzan Mazur', Scoop, (11.11.2013).
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]

  7. Müller, Vincent C. and Marsiske, Hans-Arthur (2013), 'Wir bauen keine künstlichen Menschen – Interview mit H.-A. Marsiske', C'T, KW 43 (26.10.2013), 2.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]
    Abstract: EUCog ist ein Forschungsnetzwerk, das vor knapp acht Jahren ins Leben gerufen wurde. Gegenwärtig wird es unter dem Titel EUCogIII von der Europäischen Kommission noch bis Ende 2014 gefördert. Es umfasst jetzt ungefähr 800 europäische Wissenschaftler, die sich mit künstlichen kognitiven Systemen und Robotik beschäftigen. Wir versuchen, ihnen die Möglichkeit zu geben, über grundsätzliche Fragen ihrer Forschung zu reflektieren, aber auch den Austausch mit anderen Communities zu fördern, etwa mit der industriellen Robotik oder mit Forschungen zum maschinellen Lernen.'"

  8. (2013), 'Smart robots, driverless cars work – but they bring ethical issues too' [report on EUCog Conference], The Observer, (20.10.2013), 2.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]

  9. (2011), 'Robots seek role in reactors: Artificial cognitive systems will soon be able to play a greater role in dealing with problems such as Fukushima' [Report on European Robotics Forum], Professional Engineering 24/5, 04.05.2011, 2011.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]

  10. Müller, Vincent C. and Salames, Alexandros (2009), 'Η τεχνητή νοημοσύνη είναι εργαλείο [Artificial intelligence is a Tool] - Interview by Alexandros Salames', Diadromes, Supplement to Aggelioforos, 319 (16.10.2009), 13.
    [Publisher] [PDF] [Abstract]

  11. Breuer, Ingrid; Burri, Alex and Müller, Vincent C. (1996), 'Wie realistisch kann der Realismus sein? Hilary Putnams Gratwanderung zwischen Metaphysik und Skeptizismus', Deutschlandfunk, 26.07.96, 20:10–21:00.
    [Publisher] [Abstract]
    Abstract: Wie realistisch kann der Realismus sein? Hilary Putnams Gratwanderung zwischen Metaphysik und Skeptizismus'"

1. Of course, citations (overall, per year, and h-index) are very loosely correlated to "academic quality", and not correlated to "ability". On the limitations and value of research metrics, see the Leiden Manifesto (2015) in "Nature", the DORA Manifesto (2012) and its implementation in the Netherlands (2019), and the Wikipedia entry on the h-index. Sadly, many professional philosophers refrain from making their citation 'profiles' public - though these are very useful tools.
Almost all academic disciplines have much higher citation counts than philosophy. This is because people publish more frequently, and the average publication has more references. (These factors also work favorably for philosophers who, like me, get cited in disciplines other than philosophy.)
Publication frequency (a) per person and time is about 2-5 times higher in non-humanities fields - in fact, merely the higher frequency of co-authoring would account for this difference.
Reference frequency (b) per publication differs even more. Science papers use a lot more references than philosophy papers, even though they are shorter. - Judging by journal h-index and 2007 'aggregate citation rates', they seem to be around 3-7x for social sciences or engineering, and 10x for natural sciences and medicine. Also, citations in journals are recorded well in citation indexes, citations in books less so. Finally, both publication frequency and reference frequency are increasing significantly over time.
So, for comparison across disciplines, or even fields within them 10x (2007)), one would have to multiply the two factors publication frequency and citation frequency: (a) x (b). ... In other words, such numbers are to be handled with care!